This
being Memorial Day, there are few topics worthy of such a sacred occasion. But recently, I read a book that dealt
exclusively with one such topic. I didn’t
agree with everything the book said, but the author made me think, and for that
I am appreciative.
I
wrote a short piece in response to that book and delivered it at the final
session of this season’s Washington Spinoza Society meeting last Monday. Here’s a transcript of my talk:
Shameless
hypocrites. Pathological liars. Fraudsters.
Robbers. Bullies. Serial rapists. Natural born killers. Agents of genocide. Deniers of genocide.
Those
are just a smattering of the type of people out there who make my topic such a
spicy area of interest among political philosophers. In his recent book entitled Human Dignity, Princeton Professor
George Kateb claims that, notwithstanding the variety of people’s behavior and
characters, human dignity “turns out to mean in its most common use the equal
dignity of every person.” According to
Kateb, “the dignity of every individual is equal to that of every other; which
is to say that every human being has a status
equal to that of all others.” Kateb
then goes on to say that “[T]he core idea of human dignity is that on earth,
humanity is the greatest type of being …
and that every member deserves to be treated in a manner consonant with the
high worth of the species.” For Kateb,
one doesn’t have to resort to theology to conclude that humanity transcends
nature, for humanity alone is capable of: free agency, moral agency, written
language, and self-consciousness. Human
existence and only human existence,
Kateb argues, is inward looking and able to create a sense of meaning in
life. To recognize these unique
capabilities is to understand that, in Kateb’s words, that “humanity is not only natural, whereas all other
other species are only natural,” and
“the reasons for this assertion … [have] nothing to do with theology or
religion.” Humanity is so uniquely
great, in fact, that all enlightened societies would ground themselves on a
system of human rights, which in turn rests on the notion of equal dignity for
all. Or so argues Professor Kateb.
There
is much that attracts me to Kateb’s line of thinking. But there are also elements that put me
off. For one thing, I find it ridiculous
that we have to tie our notions of human dignity to the degree of speciesism
that Kateb adopts. I’m no animal
biologist, but the idea that humans transcend nature, whereas whales and apes
do not, strikes me as bad theology and even worse science. More to the point, we don’t need to
denigrate the great apes or sea mammals in order to elevate the importance of
human dignity. In fact, we don’t even
need to assert our superiority over the other residents of this planet – the
ones that aren’t threatening climate change and aren’t responsible for
threatening the extinction of certain mammals.
Relative
to the way he compares humans to animals, Kateb’s statements about the equal
dignity of all human beings are much more compelling. But they still strike me as a bit simplistic. Let’s take the serial rapists, genocidal
maniacs – and the garden-variety politicians I referenced before. As Kateb acknowledges at one point in his
book, when you’re talking about individuals,
human dignity can be destroyed based on their conduct. Hitler is anything but dignified. To compare him, say, to Heschel in terms of
dignity seems to be at least as absurd as any comparison that can be made
between a human being and an ape or whale.
I would dare say that as individuals are concerned, the ape or whale
would be deemed much more beautiful, less heinous, and in a very colloquial
sense of the word, more “dignified” than Hitler, or his Auschwitz henchmen.
In
analyzing human dignity, I think it’s important to differentiate between our
focus on the individual and our focus on the species. It may be fair to say that when we look at
the species, we see all sorts of qualities that we deem to be exemplary. And whenever we see an individual, even if
we know nothing about that individual, we intuitively recognize his or her
potential to manifest those qualities.
We’ve already mentioned a few of them – moral agency, written language, inwardness
-- and may I add that human beings are capable of love, compassion, altruism,
great feats of scientific and literary prowess.
The list goes on.
But
when we reflect on individuals with whom we’re familiar, it is clear that the
reality may be very different. Not only
are human individuals capable of the most heinous crimes, but many aren’t
capable of much of any mental activity.
Perhaps they’re in a coma.
Perhaps they’ve had a lobotomy.
Perhaps they were born as dull in the head as Mozart was born brilliant.
Still,
we feel compelled to treat them with dignity.
And the question is, why? If they
have behaved immorally, or if they manifest far fewer mental or physical skills
than the typical chimp, why does their membership in our species nevertheless
entitle them to rights that we wouldn’t extend to members of other
species? Why do we view mental vegetables
and serial killers as deserving of our respect and compassion merely by virtue
of their species?
For
one thing, we all appreciate very vividly what happens when a society makes a
practice of ignoring human dignity for a substantial portion of the
population. The resulting acts of ugliness
and immorality are forever etched in our brains. What’s more, even when we focus on the
individual level, and not on the societal or species level, we recognize that
when a person is treated as lacking dignity, that person could very well be us
– minus a little luck. In the immortal
words of Phil Ochs, “Show me a prison, show me a jail, show me a pris’ner whose
face has grown pale, and I’ll show you a young man with many reasons why, there
but for fortune go you and go I.”
But
what truly drums in the notion of human dignity is to change the focus – away
from the slave owner or heartless bureaucrat who ignore this concept, or for
that matter the criminal or homeless person who are being denied its
protections. No, what if we consider
this concept instead from the standpoint of the privileged jurist or cleric, or
for that matter, the aristocratic poet or ingenou. These are individuals upon whom fortune has
smiled. Consider now that they are being
asked to reflect on what kind of society they wish to live in and in particular
what it means to be human in such a society.
Clearly, they will look at the matter from all angles – that of right
and wrong, good and bad, beautiful and hideous.
Which
perspective dominates their thought, no less than which conclusion they draw,
will depend on the person. But for me, I
opt for the aesthetic perspective and what it impels me to do is bestow an
inordinate amount of honor on all human beings, even those who don’t deserve it
on strictly moral grounds. You see, I
believe that it confers beauty and nobility on our species when we act as
trustees for the animals of our planet, regardless of whether they spend their
days as hunters or gatherers. Similarly,
I believe it confers beauty and nobility on ourselves and our societies when we
elevate what it means to human, regardless of whether the humans we are
elevating are gathering what is their due or hunting those who are
innocent. To make laws based on the
notion of universal dignity is to honor human potential, human achievement, and
human morality – which is frankly the only morality known to me. I would oppose capital punishment even for
those who would relish the opportunity to capitally punish others. But I would do on the grounds that to uphold
that human life is to honor the sacred importance of life generally and human
life in particular. It’s the same reason why I believe that even
the laziest among us are entitled to a significant amount of social
welfare. Not just for the sake of them
as individuals, but for the sake of our species – for what we represent as
creatures who are capable of tremendous joy or suffering, not to mention the
freedom of choice. You see, we are not
merely the sum of our past conduct and present character – we are each
combinations of person stage (past, present and future), and the lazy bum you
see one day can become a constructive member of society at some point down the
road. That assumes, of course, that our
society cultivates the dignity that this so-called “bum” possesses throughout
his life.
Ultimately,
human dignity is about recognizing all that we have in common – where we come
from, where we’re headed, what we look like, what we’re made of, how we
experience consciousness … the list is endless.
Some of us are fortunate. Others aren’t.
But let us not allow that fortune to cause us to rank one another when
it comes to what it truly most fundamental.
Just as we have no business ranking ourselves vis a vis the birds that
fly and the fish that swim, nor is it our place to decide that smart,
industrious people are somehow deserving of life, liberty and happiness,
whereas the others – well, let ‘em eat cake.
That
perspective is beneath us. It is one
thing to respect individualism as a principle of ethical and political thought. It’s another to forget that beyond our sense
of uniqueness as men or women we have an honored place as members of a species or
as expressions of the one God. You see,
Professor Kateb might think that he can derive all of his philosophical beliefs
from completely secular, areligious principles.
But I have neither such delusions nor such desires.
No comments:
Post a Comment